Showing posts with label Bioethics. Show all posts
Showing posts with label Bioethics. Show all posts

Wednesday, July 01, 2020

Dehumanizing humans

I suspect one reason some people think like this meme depicts above is because they don't have children. See declining birth rates in the US and other western nations. It's as if a baby is something "other" to them. I guess more like knowledge by description than knowledge by acquaintance. Anyway, to these people it may seem like it's an abstract debate, without significant personal stakes. That is, it's a debate between "a person with rights" vs. "a woman's right to bodily autonomy" as if "rights" is the sole or central concern, while our "humanness" is something incidental or secondary. As if "rights" are conferred by one group of human beings to another group of human beings, so it's ultimately human beings who decide which "rights" are more fundamental. They can't seem to appreciate that we're dealing with human beings who, simply by virtue of being human, have inherent or innate rights.

At best, they might see kids around them. However, they may see kids, but do they truly see kids? I know too many people or couples who "can't stand kids". Who don't wish to be around kids let alone have kids. People who are more career-minded than family-minded. (I'm referring to childless couples by choice, not childless couples who longed for children, but sadly never could have children due to infertility or other reasons.)

At the same time, it's easier to kill someone if the killer doesn't consider their victim a human being. Or considers them a lesser kind of human being. Like when Germans began to see the Jews as rats or vermin (cf. Kafka's Metamorphosis, Spiegelman's Maus). Like masters seeing slaves as their inferiors. Or like considering babies (at the embryonic or fetal stage of life) mere "clumps of cells".

People can de-God God by failing to esteem God as he ought to be esteemed, but people can also de-humanize humans by failing to esteem humans as we ought to be esteemed. Human beings aren't God, of course, but we're not a chunk of randomly assembled molecules in an aqueous solution either.

Thursday, April 30, 2020

If it saves just one life

Hovering in the background of church closures is the view that I have no right to put you at risk. Related to this is the ethical assumption that restrictions are justified "if they save just one life".

But as a matter of public policy and private behavior, no one actually operates with the principle that a restriction is justified or morally mandatory if it saves just one life. To begin with, that's hopelessly unrealistic. Life contains inevitable tradeoffs. Overprotective policies that save some lives do so at the expense of taking other lives. Policies have unintended consequences. There are no cost-free solutions. 

So what we're really dealing with is the sorites paradox or little-by-little arguments. There is no intrinsic cutoff. So it's a question of degree. How much risk is acceptable? How much is too much? How much is too little? There is no ideal answer. But we need to avoid certain extremes that lead to moral and practical paralysis of action.  

Dying young and old

1. Cultural warrior Ben Shapiro got into hot water recently by suggesting that death of the elderly from COVID19 isn't equivalent to the death of  30-something from COVID19. Shapirio is not a bioethicist, so his assessment is intuitive. There are lots of critics who wish to indulge in moral grandstanding and lobe accusations of hypocrisy rather than have a serious ethical discussion. 

2. One issue is whether it's more tragic to die young or have a natural lifespan. For instance, Mickey Mantle died shortly after a liver transplant. The question was whether the donor liver was wasted on a poor candidate. Should that have gone to a patient in a better prospect of survival? 

Dick Cheney's heart transplant at 71 was criticized. Should that go to someone with more life ahead of him? 

Not life threatening, but criticisms were raised about Prince Philip receiving a hip replacement at 96. 

3. Returning to (2), there's a sense in which the elderly have both more to lose and less to lose. On the one hand they have a cumulative lifetime of memories. A lifetime of experience.

On the other hand, the young miss out on their future. They never had those experiences. 

4. There's also the issue of squandering the gift of life. Blowing opportunities. Can you forfeit the right to demand a second chance when your second chance denies someone else a first chance? Someone who through no fault of their own never had the opportunity you abused?

5. Then there's the question of a normal lifespan. Surgery, medication, and good diet can extend life beyond what would be a natural lifespan. Is that an entitlement or a windfall? Is that something we should get used to? Should we feel cheated if we don't have a normal lifespan? Or is that a boom?

6. Artificially prolonging life carries the risk of increasing exposure to raving diseases like Parkinson's and senile dementia. So there are tradeoffs. It's tempting fate. 

7. From what I've read, the death toll for COVIN-19 is inflated by classifying the cause of death as COVIN-19 even when comorbidities were necessary contributors to death. It was the coronvirus in combination with preexisting or underlying conditions that pushed them over the edge.

8. From what I've read, we have the opposite of quarantine measures for the elderly. Rather, we round them up in retirement ohms and nursing homes which are infection vectors. They die at high rates because they infect each other and have low resistance. So if this was really about protecting the elderly, they wouldn't be concentrated in nursing homes and retirement homes where the density of exposure and low resistance guarantees high fatalities 

9. Death is inevitable. We can sometimes postpone the inevitable, but the ultimate issue is the significance of human life. Is this life all there is? What ultimately matters is not how long you live but what's in store for you when you die. 

10. Theologically, it's an interesting question what constitutes a normal or natural lifespan. As I read Genesis, humans were naturally mortal, naturally subject to the aging process, but they were created with the unrealized capacity for immortality. They'd naturally age and died, perhaps at a slower rate, but the potential for immortality wasn't automatic. Rather, that's a gift conferred by the tree of life. And for the dead in Christ, that's reversed by the resurrection of the just. 

Tuesday, March 17, 2020

Planned Parenthood coughs on pro-lifers

Saturday, February 29, 2020

"There are no unborn children in science"

1. Philosopher Kyle Blanchette responded to Gunter and her ilk months ago.

2. The basic issue is that

Friday, February 21, 2020

Same person, different location

Someone recently posted this image of their baby:


(Source)

Pete Buttigieg said:

Now right now, they [pro-life Christians] hold everyone in line with this one kind of piece of doctrine about abortion, right? Which is obviously a tough issue for a lot of people to think through morally. Then again, you know, there are a lot of parts of the Bible that talk about how life begins with breath. And so even that is something we can interpret differently.

Mayor Pete assumes a baby doesn't "breathe" until the baby has been born and starts crying. I've pointed out how that's a false assumption.

Monday, February 17, 2020

First breath

Mayor Pete:

In an interview on CBS' "Breakfast Club," the good mayor suggested that not only is a full-term baby girl, who is in the process of exiting her mother’s birth canal, not yet a human being, but neither is that same child post-birth, when she is held in the doctor’s hands.

No, a beating heart, the sensations of pain and pleasure, and the ability to move her legs, arms, fingers and toes do not grant this infant personhood, dignity and the right to life.

None of these things matter, says Mayor Pete. A baby is not human, nor does it warrant any legal protection, until after it takes its first breath.

https://www.washingtontimes.com/news/2020/feb/14/presidential-candidate-pete-buttigieg-insults-the-

1. Mayor Pete is morally reprehensible.

2. What is breathing? There are several ways to answer this question. I'll simplify, but I can delve into the technical details if necessary. Minimally, or essentially, I'd say breathing is gas exchange. Mainly oxygen and carbon dioxide as far as humans are concerned. Breathing is the movement of oxygen into the body and the movement of carbon dioxide out of the body.

3. Babies in the womb do, in fact, exchange gas. Hence, on this definition, babies are breathing in the womb. Of course, babies aren't breathing with fully functional lungs like we are. The main reason for this is because (at the risk of stating the obvious) a baby's lungs are still being formed in the womb. Nevertheless the baby is breathing, oxygenating, ventilating, exchanging oxygen and carbon dioxide, perfusing cells and tissues and organs.

4. As such, Mayor Pete's criterion that a baby is only a human after it takes its first breath is preposterous. The baby has been breathing the entire time.

5. Mayor Pete seems to think breathing is something that happens when one can observe the diaphragm contracting, muscles moving, chest rising, and the like. However that's a mechanistic understanding of what breathing is. Breathing strictly as mechanics. But what's the purpose of our diaphragm contracting, muscles moving, and lungs working?

To put it another way, everyone needs oxygen to live, and in newborns and adults oxygen is best obtained via our lungs, but that doesn't necessarily imply our lungs are the only means by which we can obtain oxygen.

6. Otherwise, if we consistently applied this mechanistic position, then a baby or adult who can't breathe without the assistance of modern ventilators (or in the past an iron lung) is "not human, nor does it warrant legal protection". Likewise a drowned person who can be revived with CPR but whose lungs aren't currently expanding and contracting is "not human, nor does it warrant legal protection". A newborn or adult on a heart-lung (cardiopulmonary) bypass machine is "not human, nor does it warrant legal protection".

Thursday, February 13, 2020

Zombie preparedness in real life

Horror stories about werewolves, vampires, and zombies allegorize epidemics and pandemics. Werewolves, vampires, and zombies are contagious. Each individual can infect a number of healthy humans. These in turn can infect a number of healthy human beings, so that the initial outbreak can spread at an exponential rate and quickly spiral out of control, leading to the collapse of civilization. 

Werewolves are asymptomatic carriers except during a full moon. Vampires are largely asymptomatic carriers although there are telltale signs if you know what to look for (fangs, aversion to light, lack of vital signs), so they must take precautions to avoid detection. 

Quarantine is a classic response to infectious disease. The success of quarantine depends in part on the incubation period. In some cases you have asymptomatic carriers who unwittingly infect others. By the time they become symptomatic, the disease has spread. It's too late to round them up. 

STDs can be another example of asymptomatic carriers. In some cases the carrier may be aware of the STD, but conceals his condition and continues to infect others.

In scifi lore, werewolves, vampires, and zombies are killed without compunction in part because they are dangerous to humans and in part because they are inhuman or subhuman. Vampires are lucid serial killers. Werewolves have lupine psychology at the time they kill, while zombies operate at an instinctual level.  

Some zombie flicks are comedies while others use the genre for social commentay. Zombie preparedness alerts and kits are humorous. The zombie apocalypse is a humorous trope. 

This is all fictional (except for STDs) but it has real-world counterparts. As I write, we are witnessing the Coronavirus. It remains to be seen how damaging that outbreak will be. 

Because we're social creatures, many humans have compassion for the sick and injured. That, however, depends on whether the sick and injured are perceived as posing a threat to healthy members of the population. 

Quarantine is a classic response to outbreak but quarantine isn't risk free because it requires some contact between the sick and the healthy. The OT has quarantine laws. It was humanitarian.

A more ruthless impulse is to contain an outbreak by killing the infected. And since carriers may be asymptotic, to kill everyone within a designated zone to provide a margin for error. A fictional example is 28 Weeks Later.

In an atheist regime like Red China, we see real-world analogies. The idea of risking your life to nurse the sick is a very Christian impulse. It taps into moral heroism. And it makes sense if you can afford to die because this life is not all there is. 

But atheists don't have that luxury. So the gov't is welding residential buildings closed. Sealing all the residents inside, sick and healthy alike, to die en masse from disease or starvation, dehydration, and lack of sanitation. 

Wednesday, February 12, 2020

Behold the beauty of atheism

See how an atheist regime deals with an epidemic:



Traditionally, Christians founded the hospitals. Caring for the sick was very hazardous before the advent of antibiotics and antivirals since the caretaker could easily become infected and die from the same contagious disease. It takes faith and courage to care for patients with a life-threatening disease if that's life-threatening to the caregiver. Whether you're prepared to risk your own life to nurse others back to health depends in part on whether you think this life is all there is. This is an acid test of atheism. 

Due to sin, there are cowardly Christians. Due to common grace, there are courageous atheists. But I'm remarking on the logical outworking of competing worldviews. This is the same regime that engages in involuntary organ harvesting. 

Friday, November 08, 2019

Chinese organ-harvesting


Communist Chinese organ-harvesting is a diabolical, but clarifying illustration of consistent atheism. Human beings are just meat machines with an expiration date, manufactured other meat machines. The stronger machines strip the weaker machines for spare parts. There is no good or evil, right or wrong, just the powerful and the powerless. Unsentimental atheism.

Wednesday, October 23, 2019

Dad tries to save son from transgenderism

And to piggyback on Steve's post as well:

1. If all the reports are accurate, then I couldn't agree more. It's maddening, infuriating, lamentable. The kid has no more hope for a happy childhood.

2. Not to mention by all accounts I've read the 7 year old boy doesn't want to be a girl but his mother is forcing her choice onto the boy. Does this set a precedence for parents to transition their children into a different sex against their children's wills? At this point, it looks like progressives are arguing women should be able to abort their child even as newborns no longer in the womb and women should be able to turn their children into whatever sex they wish their children to be despite biological realities. Is there anything women can't do to their children according to progressives?

3. The mother is a pediatrician who should know better. However she's a terrible and evil person. Indeed, it seems to me there are many women like her.

4. Women have had a loud and clear voice for generations, but who will speak on behalf of men? Men seem to be increasingly unfairly discriminated against in our society. Boys and men are increasingly tyrannized by third wave feminists and progressives in general. For example, Christina Hoff Sommers has documented a lot of this.

5. I don't know if there's any more hope for the father to win a court case. I don't know if he can appeal. Or even take it to the Supreme Court.

6. However, if there are no more legal options open to the father, and assuming most people bow to the evil judicial decision, then if it were me I think I'd consider trying to "kidnap" my son (in fact both of my sons since they're twins) and fleeing to another state or even another nation. I realize this is desperate, but I don't know what else the father can do. It seems he's only left with hard choices for his sons: a choice between state-sponsored child abuse under an evil mother in the US vs. a more normal childhood under a good father but living life on the run. But I think this kind of "kidnapping" is arguably justifiable on Christian ethics.

7. Remember this case whenever you hear liberals and progressives say things like "transgenderism doesn't harm anyone", "transgenderism is not a mental illness", "everyone should get a choice", "it's their choice, not yours", "you're bigoted against transgendered peoples", etc. The truth is liberals and progressives are always pushing their abnormal values onto normal people, but acting like they're the victims when normal people dissent.

What is death?

The following is an excerpt from Louis Pojman's book Life and Death (1992), pp 158-164. It discusses criteria for death as well as organ transplantation. I strongly disagree with Pojman on these matters. However, he gives a decent enough summary of the main categories for death and related issues that I'll quote it here. In addition, Pojman's argument (which was made in 1992) doesn't seem substantially different from how progressive ethicists argue today. I'll have to interact with Pojman at a later time.

Wednesday, July 17, 2019

Planned Parenthood fires Wen

Planned Parenthood (PP) recently fired its president, Dr. Leana Wen, who is an emergency physician. My thoughts:

Tuesday, July 02, 2019

Informed consent

1. Glad to see a pro-life victory.

2. As a possible aid for pro-lifers in general, let me mention two words: informed consent.

Here I'll emphasize the "informed" in informed consent.

What is informed consent? At a basic level, my understanding is informed consent is the idea that the patient ought to be given the choice to accept or decline medical treatment based on the physician (or other health care providers) providing the patient comprehensible and sufficient information to make this choice (e.g. relevant knowledge of risks and benefits of medical treatment).

In short, patients need to know what medical treatment they're receiving with their eyes as wide open as possible.

Of course, there may be exceptions (e.g. an unconscious patient with life-threatening trauma that requires immediate action), but I'm speaking in general.

At least this is my working definition, but I presume a lawyer, ethicist, and/or philosopher could improve upon it. I'd be glad to have an improved definition.

3. In any case, showing a woman seeking an abortion an ultrasound of her baby, explaining what everything means to her, and fielding any questions she has in order to obtain consent for abortion seems to me to be part and parcel of informed consent. It seems to me it's what a physician is obligated to do with respect to informed consent.

4. At the same time, intentionally withholding this same information seems to me the physician is failing to obtain adequate informed consent. As such, it seems to me the physician could be liable to a charge of negligence.

5. Suppose someone is seeking quadruple bypass heart surgery. Suppose the cardiothoracic surgeon intentionally withholds relevant information about what the surgery will involve. This could open the cardiothoracic surgeon to a malpractice suit.

I'm no lawyer, ethicist, or philosopher, but perhaps a case could be made that it should be the same for physicians and other health care providers who refuse to provide information to women seeking an abortion like ultrasounds and hearing their baby's heart beat. If so, then we can take the fight to pro-abortionists.

Thursday, June 20, 2019

Mercy-killing and wedge issues

Let's begin with two examples, one fictional and the other real:

A. At a mine cave-in, Joe's friend Seth Pruitt stands over the body of a man he admits to having euthanized. The man was mortally injured, in agony, and begging to be put out of his misery. Seth swears Joe to secrecy, leaving Joe to struggle with his conscience, and decide if it's right to keep the secret. "The Quality of Mercy," Bonanza (Season 5 Episode 9).

B. Years ago I read about a father and sons who were horribly burned when the garage that were working in exploded. They weren't killed instantly. They were mortally burned and die hours later at the hospital. That's not a case of euthanasia, but for those who support euthanasia, it's a good candidate to illustrate the issues.

1. On the one hand there are ethicists, generally Christian, who think euthanasia is intrinsically wrong. For convenience, let's call it the deontologist position. 

One apparent advantage of the deontologist position is that it seems to be simpler to apply. It forbids mercy killing under any circumstances. I'll revisit the question of whether it avoids the complications and imponderables of the alternative position momentarily. 

2. In addition to the argument from principle, the deontologist is concerned that once you open the door a crack for mercy killing under any circumstances, that becomes a wedge issue or wedge tactic which will be exploited. And, indeed, that's a legitimate and very realistic concern. Once euthanasia is permitted, there are those who continually extent and expand the scope of candidates for euthanasia. A mania for killing ensues. This has been documented by Wesley J. Smith: https://www.discovery.org/c/human-exceptionalism/

3. On the other hand are ethicists who think euthanasia is permissible in certain situations. Some ethicists are very conservative about the permissibility of euthanasia, limiting it to "extreme" cases. Others are far more lenient. For convenience, let's call it the euthanasist position.  

These labels are simplistic. On the one hand it's possible for a deontologist to consider mercy killing justifiable under very exceptional circumstances. On the other hand, euthanasist is an indiscriminate term. Proponents of euthanasia can range along a continuum from highly restrictive to open-ended. But labels are necessary to identify and distinguish the respective positions, so with those caveats in place, they will suffice for discussion purposes. 

4. A challenge for the euthansist position is where to draw the line. 

i) That raises the thorny old issue of the sorites paradox. However, the sorites paradox doesn't necessarily disqualify the euthanasist position. The sorites paradox isn't confined to ethics. There are many situations in human experience susceptible to soritical paradox, yet we disregard it and go right on drawing moral or practical distinctions, even if we can't solve the paradox. 

ii) In addition, we're often confronted with forced options where we have no choice but to draw a line, even if the cutoff is arbitrary. If, moreover, you can't avoid stipulating an arbitrary threshold, then a degree of arbitrariness is blameless. 

iii) That's said, some arbitrary distinctions are more reasonable than others. While there are borderline cases, some distinctions approximate clear boundary conditions.

5. For its own part, the deontologist position doesn't escape the sorites paradox. Even hardline opponents of euthanasia typically concede that there are moral limits on our duty to keep people alive. Take a terminal cancer patient with stage 4  cancer. Desperate medical intervention may prolong the patient's life, but the treatment itself is increasingly destructive to the patient, with ever diminishing returns. 

If, however, the obligation to keep people alive is less than absolute, then that concession creates gray areas. In a sense, then, both the deontologist and euthanasist are in the same boat, although one may occupy the stem while the other occupies the stern. 

6. Regarding the Bonanza dilemma, there are two additional issues:

i) On the one hand, Seth has no right to obligate Joe to keep Seth's action a secret. He lacks the moral authority to unilaterally make that decision for Joe. At best, Joe must enter into that voluntarily.

ii) On the other hand, even if we conclude that Seth's action was morally unjustified, that doesn't automatically mean Joe has a duty to report him to the authorities. This is the flip side of (i). Just as Seth can't make Joe share responsibility in the deed, since it's Seth's deed, not Joe's, Joe is not responsible for what Seth did.

To put it another way, even if Seth had a duty to turn himself in to the authorities, it doesn't follow that a second party has a duty to turn Seth in to the authorities. A second party isn't directly responsible for Seth's actions.

iii) Of course, that doesn't mean there's never an obligation to report a wrongdoing to the authorities. But that's not a universal duty. It depends on the nature of the wrongdoing.

iv) Moreover, even if we conclude that Seth's action is morally unjustifiable, there are extenuating circumstances that mitigate the guilt and distinguish it from murder. The intent is different. 

v) Likewise, we should often judge people more leniently who had to make a snap decision under duress compared to a premeditated action. 

7. There is, however, a difference between the actions of random individuals and a social policy. For instance, if my younger teenage brother loses his temper and smacks me in the face, I'm not going to call the cops, have him arrested and charged with assault. But making personal exceptions for close relatives doesn't mean we should decriminalize assault and battery. 

8. Finally, I doubt that all moral dilemmas are soluble in principle. It's easy to dream of hypothetical predicaments with no licit options. There won't always be a handy formula. I think we ultimately depend, not on having the right answers for every conceivable situation, but on divine providence not to put us in morally compromising situations.