hide
Named Entity Searches
hide
Sorting
You can sort these results in two ways:
- By entity
- Chronological order for dates, alphabetical order for places and people.
- By position (current method)
- As the entities appear in the document.
You are currently sorting in ascending order. Sort in descending order.
hide
Most Frequent Entities
The entities that appear most frequently in this document are shown below.
Entity | Max. Freq | Min. Freq | ||
---|---|---|---|---|
Athens (Greece) | 22 | 0 | Browse | Search |
Sparta (Greece) | 10 | 0 | Browse | Search |
Scythia | 6 | 0 | Browse | Search |
Troy (Turkey) | 4 | 0 | Browse | Search |
Corinth (Greece) | 2 | 0 | Browse | Search |
Argos (Greece) | 2 | 0 | Browse | Search |
Thebes (Greece) | 2 | 0 | Browse | Search |
Amphipolis (Greece) | 2 | 0 | Browse | Search |
Megara (Greece) | 2 | 0 | Browse | Search |
Crete (Greece) | 2 | 0 | Browse | Search |
View all entities in this document... |
Browsing named entities in Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics (ed. H. Rackham).
Found 115 total hits in 39 results.
Thebes (Greece) (search for this): book 3, chapter 1
Yet there seem to be some acts which a man cannot be compelled to
do,i.e., some acts are so repulsive that a man's
abhorrence of them must be stronger than any pressure that can be put on him to commit
them; so that if he commits them he must be held to have chosen to do so. and
rather than do them he ought to submit to the most terrible death: for instance, we think
it ridiculous that Alcmaeon in Euripides' playIn a
play now lost, Eriphyle was bribed with a necklace to induce her husband Amphiaraus,
king of Argos, to join the expedition of the
Seven against Thebes. Foreseeing he would lose
his life, he charged his sons to avenge his death upon their mother, invoking on them
famine and childlessness if they disobeyed. The verse in question is preserved: ma/lista me\n m' e)ph=r' e)piskh/yas path/r. Alcmaeon, fr. 69
(Nauck). is compelled by certain threats to murder his mother!
Argos (Greece) (search for this): book 3, chapter 1
Yet there seem to be some acts which a man cannot be compelled to
do,i.e., some acts are so repulsive that a man's
abhorrence of them must be stronger than any pressure that can be put on him to commit
them; so that if he commits them he must be held to have chosen to do so. and
rather than do them he ought to submit to the most terrible death: for instance, we think
it ridiculous that Alcmaeon in Euripides' playIn a
play now lost, Eriphyle was bribed with a necklace to induce her husband Amphiaraus,
king of Argos, to join the expedition of the
Seven against Thebes. Foreseeing he would lose
his life, he charged his sons to avenge his death upon their mother, invoking on them
famine and childlessness if they disobeyed. The verse in question is preserved: ma/lista me\n m' e)ph=r' e)piskh/yas path/r. Alcmaeon, fr. 69
(Nauck). is compelled by certain threats to murder his mother!
Lydia (Turkey) (search for this): book 1, chapter 10
Are we then to count no other human being happy either, as long as he is alive? Must we
obey Solon's warning,See Hdt.
1.30-33. Solon visited Croesus, king of Lydia, and was shown all his treasures, but refused to call him the
happiest of mankind until he should have heard that he had ended his life without
misfortune; he bade him ‘mark the end of every matter, how it should turn
out.’ and ‘look to the end’? And if we are indeed to lay down this rule, can a man really be happy
after he is dead? Surely that is an extremely strange notion, especially for us who define
happiness as a form of activity! While if on the other
hand we refuse to speak of a dead man as happy, and Solon's words do not mean this, but
that only when a man is dead can one safely call him blessed as being now beyond the reach
of evil and misfortune, this also admits of some dispute; for it is believed that some
evil and also some good can befall the de
Lesbos (Greece) (search for this): book 5, chapter 10
Athens (Greece) (search for this): book 8, chapter 10
Athens (Greece) (search for this): book 5, chapter 11
Crete (Greece) (search for this): book 1, chapter 13
But inasmuch as happiness is a certain activity of soul in conformity with perfect
virtue, it is necessary to examine the nature of virtue. For this will probably assist us
in our investigation of the nature of happiness. Also,
the true statesman seems to be one who has made a special study of goodness, since his aim
is to make the citizens good and law-abiding men—witness the lawgivers of Crete and Sparta, and the other great legislators of history;
but if the study of virtue falls within the province of
Political Science, it is clear that in investigating virtue we shall be keeping to the
plan which we laid down at the outset.
Now the goodness that we have to consider is clearly human virtue, since the good or
happiness which we set out to seek is human good and human happiness. But human virtue means in our view excellence of soul, not excellence of
body; also our definition of happiness is an activity of the soul. Now if this i
Sparta (Greece) (search for this): book 1, chapter 13
But inasmuch as happiness is a certain activity of soul in conformity with perfect
virtue, it is necessary to examine the nature of virtue. For this will probably assist us
in our investigation of the nature of happiness. Also,
the true statesman seems to be one who has made a special study of goodness, since his aim
is to make the citizens good and law-abiding men—witness the lawgivers of Crete and Sparta, and the other great legislators of history;
but if the study of virtue falls within the province of
Political Science, it is clear that in investigating virtue we shall be keeping to the
plan which we laid down at the outset.
Now the goodness that we have to consider is clearly human virtue, since the good or
happiness which we set out to seek is human good and human happiness. But human virtue means in our view excellence of soul, not excellence of
body; also our definition of happiness is an activity of the soul. Now if this is
Athens (Greece) (search for this): book 3, chapter 2
Also we may wish for what cannot
be secured by our own agency, for instance, that a particular actorGreek dramas were produced in competitions (and it is noteworthy
that in the Old Comedy at Athens the play
itself dramatized a contest or debate). or athlete may win; but no one
chooses what does not rest with himself, but only what he thinks can be attained by his
own a
Athens (Greece) (search for this): book 4, chapter 2
Next it would seem proper to discuss Magnificence,megalopre/peia denotes Munificence of a magnificent
kind, the spending of money on a grand scale from the motive of public spirit. In
discussing it Aristotle is thinking especially of the lh|tourgi/ai or public services discharged at Athens, and in other Greek cities, by wealthy individuals; such as the
refitting of a naval trireme, the equipment of a dramatic chorus, and the defraying of
the cost of a qewri/a or delegation representing the
State at one of the great Hellenic festivals. The word literally means ‘great
conspicuousness’ or splendor, but in eliciting its connotation Aristotle
brings in another meaning of the verb pre/pein, viz.
‘to be fitting,’ and takes the noun to signify
‘suitability on a great scale’; and also he feels that the element
‘great’ denotes grandeur as well as mere magnitude. for this
also appears to be a virtue concerned with wealth.