This work is available here free, so that those who cannot afford it can still have access to it, and so that no one has to pay before they read something that might not be what they really are seeking. But if you find it meaningful and helpful and would like to contribute whatever easily affordable amount you feel it is worth, please do do. I will appreciate it. The button to the right will take you to PayPal where you can make any size donation (of 25 cents or more) you wish, using either your PayPal account or a credit card without a PayPal account. |
Jack Meiland and Richard Taylor, Spatio-Temporal Analogy Richard Taylor[1] has argued that time and space (or perhaps
more accurately, temporal relations and spatial relations) are far more alike
or analogous than one might think. Jack
Meiland[2] in
answer to Taylor has argued that time and space or temporal and spatial relations
are not so analogous as Taylor might think.
Meiland has pointed out what he considers to be a neglect or confusion
in Taylor's argument. In this paper I
wish (1) to point out what that confusion is
(2) to show that with the proper distinctions Taylor’s arguments escape
Meiland's criticisms (3) to show that
Meiland himself falls victim to a very similar confusion[3] and (4) to present an aspect in which space and
time or spatial and temporal relations do appear to be disanalogous. I will construct my
analogies in the same way both Taylor and Meiland do, by exchanging every
spatial term in a statement with the corresponding temporal term and vice
versa. First, however, I should like to
make a few distinctions. Let us assume that
all objects consist of and are the sum total of (except for arrangement) units
we shall call spatio-temporal parts -- parts which have some size and last for
some time. These units are to be
arbitrarily small both in size and duration; just as ordinarily we conceive of
spatial parts as being able to be arbitrarily small. And, although I will not
argue for it, I would think that these spatio-temporal parts would be either
limited or unlimited as to brevity of size and duration in the same way
ordinarily spatial parts are limited to size—i.e., if the smallest conceivable
spatial part must be some finite size and if the smallest conceivable temporal
parts must be some finite duration, then the smallest conceivable
spatio-temporal units would probably also have to be of some finite spatial and
temporal length. But if no logical or
practical difficulties follow from considering either the smallest temporal or
spatial parts (here again relying on the common notion of a spatial part—e.g.,
gears are spatial parts of a watch, cogs are spatial parts of a gear, etc.)as
being infinitely small (difficulties such as 'but then no matter how many you had
together, they would still be invisible because they would still take up no
space or time, etc.'), then I should imagine none would follow from considering
the smallest spatio-temporal parts as infinitely small in either or both size
and duration. Now at different
times an object will consist of different spatio-temporal parts. For instance an old man consists of different
spatio-temporal parts from those of himself as a baby; this is by virtue of the
'flow of time' since he still has the same basic 'spatial parts' (ordinary
sense of spatial parts as above), fingers, eyes, feet, etc. And at any given
time an object will have different spatio-temporal parts by virtue of its
having different spatial parts (again, ordinary sense of spatial parts), e.g.,
at any given time a man has different spatio-temporal parts because he has
different spatial parts-fingers, eyes, feet, etc. Taking then the idea
of a spatio-temporal part as primitive I wish to define (technically, though I
think closely allied to common usage) (1) a temporal part, t, of an object 0 as
all the spatio-temporal parts of 0 at a given time T. (2) a spatial part, p,
of an object 0 as all the spatio-temporal parts of 0 at any given place (or
slice') P. For example, the
temporal part of me at my birth is or was all 7 Ibs. 15 oz. of me then; spatial
parts of me are my fingers, lungs, etc. Now there can be spatial part of
temporal parts and temporal parts of spatial parts; and in fact 'the temporal
part tx of spatial part px of an object' is or refers to the same
spatio-temporal part(s) as 'the spatial part px of temporal part tx
of an object.' For example, a spatial
part of me at my birth --a temporal part of me-- is or was my right index
finger then, just as my right index finger at birth is or was a temporal part
of my right index finger --a spatial part of me. Of course, also
temporal parts may have temporal parts just as spatial parts may have spatial
parts. E.g., my right index finger has
three bones, skin, etc.; the 'me' of February 1967 was made of the
"me's" of February 1, February 2, February 3, etc. of 1967. Now on page 4 of his
paper Meiland claims: "But even if
we do say that temporal parts have spatial_parts_of this sort, there is still a
crucial similarity between spatial parts of physical objects_and temporal parts
of physical objects. [Meiland, of course, is not necessarily using
my 'technical' notion of "temporal parts" or "spatial
parts," but the 'common sense' notion of such, which may be confused or
which may differ in some other way from my definition.] For spatial parts of physical objects are
composed wholly of temporal parts, but temporal parts of physical objects
are not composed wholly of spatial aspects.
If a Taylorian analogy existed between spatial and temporal parts of
physical objects, then both of the following statements wouId be true: "(S1): A spatial part of a physical object can be
regarded as a set of temporal parts. "(S2):
A temporal part of a physical object can be regarded as a set of spatial parts (of the sort known
as 'spatial aspects'). "Statement
S1 is true. But what could
statement S2 mean? We might
try to give S2 a meaning in this way. Suppose that the temporal part of X in
question is (T3 – T7).
This temporal part has its own temporal parts,
namely (T3-T4), (T4-T5, (T5-T6),
and (T6-T7). And each of the
latter has a spatial aspect. So it might
be thought that the temporal part (T3-T7) could be
regarded as the set of these spatial aspects, that is, as the set of spatial
aspects of its own temporal parts. This
would provide a meaning for statement S2 but it would also render S2
false. For even with the set of these
spatial aspects, there is still something missing from temporal part (T3
– T7), namely its temporal aspect.
Hence the temporal part (T3 – T7) cannot be
regarded as composed wholly of spatial elements. This temporal part is not the set of certain
spatial aspects." Elsewhere after extended argument (pp. 3 and
4) Meiland correctly concludes what is present in the temporal part of an
object is not the spatial parts themselves, but rather temporal parts of those
spatial parts. The non-underlined portions of the above
offer a very astute observation, but the underlined statements are simply
false. S1 is false or meaningless as is S2. A Taylorian analogy does not say both S1
and S2 must be true, but that they must both have the same truth
value (both can be false) or both be meaningless. Meiland gives S2 a meaning, a
meaning which he correctly argues renders it false. But as it stands, S1,
though Meiland thinks it to be true, is also either meaningless or false, for
contrary to Meiland's statement, spatial parts of physical objects are not
composed wholly of temporal parts, just as (as Meiland correctly claims)
temporal parts of physical objects are not composed wholly of spatial aspects. I will accept Meiland's argument and
(particularly) his conclusion that a temporal part of a physical object must
have both spatial and temporal aspects -- and consider his paper as offering
support for my definition of temporal part.
Now I wish to support a bit more my definition of spatial part and argue
that Meiland’s S1 is false if given a meaning in the same way that
he gave S2 a meaning. Paraphrasing Meiland in the last above quoted
paragraph: Suppose that the
spatial part [in Meiland's or Taylor's or common-sense notion of spatial part,
disregarding my definition whether it characterizes that notion or not] of 0 in
question is (P3 - P7) (e. g., say my right index
finger). This spatial part has its own spatial
parts, namely (P3-P4), (P4-P5), (P5-P6),
and (P6-P7) (say, bones, muscle, skin, nail). And each of the latter has a temporal
aspect. So it might be thought that the
spatial part (P3-P7) could be regarded as the set of
these temporal aspects, that is as the set of temporal aspects of its own
spatial parts. This would provide a
meaning for statement S1 but it would also render S1
false. For even with the set of these temporal
aspects, there is still something missing from spatial part (P3–P7),
namely its spatial aspect. Hence the
spatial part (P3–P7) cannot be regarded as composed
wholly of temporal elements. This
spatial part is not the set of certain temporal aspects.-- BUT OF TEMPORAL AND SPATIAL
ASPECTS; OF SPATIO-TEMPORAL PARTS. If at T1 I cut off my
finger and look at the cross section of bone, muscle, skin, etc. I do not see
things that only endure through time; I see things which also take up
space-bone, muscle, skin, etc. Likewise, as Meiland might argue, if I take a
temporal part of me, say me now, I do
not just have a chunk of material which takes up space, but a part which also
takes up time, which endures -- for as long as 'now' 'endures.' With this as background I should now like (1)
to review the analogies of Taylor's which Meiland reviewed (2) to try to get the correct or precise
statement of each analogue according to definitions 1 and 2 and the notion of
spatio-temporal parts and (3) to try to
show that Taylor's original statements using my definitions of temporal parts
and spatial parts gives the analogies he sought. I shall exchange temporal terms for spatial
terms and vice versa, but will consider there to be no analogue to the term
spatio-temporal, considering this term to be equally characteristic of both
spatial and temporal relations, of both space and time, being neither more a
space term than a time term nor vice versa.
I shall not go into detail as to what phenomena or objects can actually
represent the objects portrayed in these analogues; Taylor does, and I shall simply
refer to his examples, presupposing that the reader is familiar with those
examples. I. A: Entities can move in space. Taylor A; At T1, 01 is north of O2.
At T2, 01 is south of 02. Meiland A: At T1,
temporal part N of 01 is north of temporal part G of 02. At
T2, temporal part S of 01 is south of temporal part H of
02. Garlikov A: At T1, spatio-temporal part N of 01
is north of spatio-temporal part G of 02. At T2, spatio-temporal part S of 01
is south of spatio-temporal part H of 02. B (the
analogue): Entities
can move in time. -- e.g., an
earthquake’s occurring before the stroke of a clock in one town and after that
stroke of the clock in another town. Taylor B; At P1, 01 is future to
02. At P2, 01 is past to 02. Meiland B: At P1 temporal part F of 01
is future to 02. At P2 temporal part Q of 01
is past to 02, [which is not a real analogue to Meiland A as Meiland
correctly points out]. However, Meiland does
not present statement or situation B correctly (disregarding his representation
of A) because F and P are not only different temporal parts of the earthquake,
but also different spatial parts (hence, different spatio-temporal parts) given
that earthquakes are the types of things that have spatio-temporal parts. And it would seem that if an earthquake can
be said to have different temporal parts, parts which occur at different times,
then it can be said to have different spatial parts -- parts which occur at
different places. Hence, it could be
said: Garlikov B: At P1 spatio-temporal part F of 01
is future to spatio-temporal part R of 02. At L2 spatio-temporal part P of 01
is past to spatio-temporal M of 02. This is analogous to Garlikov A since “spatio-temporal”
is not one of the terms needed to be exchanged in the statement (or perhaps some
might wish to say it changes to tempero-spatial, which would be the same thing
as spatio-temporal). Notice further that if we substitute '01'
for 'spatio-temporal part F (a part of 01 occurring at some time and
place, place P1) of 01'
and if we substitute '01' also for 'spatio-temporal part P of
01' in Garlikov B, and if in Garlikov B we also substitute '02'
for both 's-t part R of 02' and 's-t part M of 02' we get
Taylor B. Making a similar substitution in Garlikov A
we get Taylor A.[4] Further this is the type of substitution we
make all the time in everyday usage. We
do call both the earthquake in town P1 at T1 and the
earthquake in town P2 at T2 'the' earthquake or "the
same' earthquake, though to be accurate or precise we should perhaps refer to
them as different spatio-temporal parts of 'the' earthquake, assuming, of
course, that we still wish to speak about 'the' earthquake. Likewise we call the face or whole body of
Rick Garlikov now when we see it “Rick Garlikov” just as we called the facial
or all 7 Ibs. 15 oz. spatio-temporal part of Rick Garlikov some 62 years ago “Rick
Garlikov” when we looked toward the blanket and saw it.[5] We often refer to the spatio-temporal part of
a thing as the whole thing. Hence, here, Taylor A and Taylor B are analogous
when interpreted as Garlikov A and Garlikov B respectively, these latter two
being analogous. And this interpretation
does in fact reflect ordinary usage, though perhaps it might be better,
ordinary language might be more clear (though more cumbersome) if it were of
the expanded Garlikov form, rather than in the Taylor form as it is now. II. A: An entity can be at two times in one place. Taylor A: 0 is at P1 at T1 and T2. Meiland A: At P1,
a temporal part of 0 is at T1 and another temporal part of 0 is at T2. But, since temporal parts (on
Meiland's notion of temporal parts, not just my technical notion) cannot exist
without spatial aspects, what must be the case is: Garlikov A: At P1 a spatio-temporal part of
0 is at T1 and another spatio-temporal part of 0 is at T2. B: An entity can be at
two places at the same time. Taylor B: 0 is at T1 at P1 and P2. Meiland B: At T1 a temporal part of 0 is at P1
and P2. Garlikov B: (for the same reasons as above) At T1 a spatio-temporal part of 0
is at P1 and another spatio-temporal part of 0 is at P2. Again here in II, as in I, with a
normal substitution (i.e., referringto a spatio-temporal part of a thing as the
whole thing) we get Taylor A and Taylor B from Garlikov A and Garlikov B
respectively. Hence, Taylor A and Taylor
B are or can be analogous as Taylor claimed, since Garlikov A and Garlikov B
are analogous. III.A: Things can move closer together or farther apart in space. Taylor A: At T1, temporal part 1 of object 01
and temporal part 1 of object 02 are separated
by a spatial interval x. At T2, temporal part 2 of
object 01 and temporal part 2 of object 02 are separated
by a spatial interval y, y being either smaller or larger than x. Meiland A: Same as Taylor A, I believe. Garlikov A: At T1, spatio-temporal part 1 of
object 01 and spatio-temporal part 1 of object 02 are
separated by a spatial interval x. At T2, spatio-temporal part 2 of
object 01 and spatio-temporal part 2 of object 02 are
separated by a spatial interval y, y being either smaller or larger than x. B. Objects can move
closer together or father apart in time. Taylor B: At P1, spatial part 1 of object 01
and spatial part 1 of object 02 are separated by a temporal interval
X. At T2, spatial part 2 of object 01 and spatial part 2 of
object 02 are separated by a temporal interval Y, Y being either
smaller or larger than X. Meiland B: At P1 temporal part 1 of 01
and temporal part 1 of 02 are separated by a temporal interval X. At
P2 temporal part 2 of 01 and temporal part 2 of 02 are
separated by a temporal interval Y, Y being either smaller or larger than X. Garlikov B: (again since strictly speaking there can be
no temporal parts on Meiland's or Taylor's notion without spatial aspects, just
as there can be no spatial parts on Meiland's or Taylor's or the common sense
notion of spatial parts without temporal aspects) At P1,
spatio-temporal part 1 of 01 and spatio-temporal part 1 of 02
are separated by a temporal interval X. At P2, spatio-temporal part
2 of 01 and spatio-temporal part 2 of 02 are separated by
a temporal interval Y, Y being either larger er smaller than X. Garlikov B is analogous to Garlikov A,
and although Meiland B is not analogous to Meiland A, that is because Meiland
has again not seen that spatial parts have temporal aspects, although he has
noticed that temporal parts have spatial aspects. What is heard when one hears the two rolls of
thunder in different places at different times (Taylor's example here) is both
different spatial and different temporal parts of 'the' thunder. And, if in Taylor's account, one
understands 'spatial parts' and 'temporal parts' as I have above technically
defined them -- as each having both temporal and spatial aspects by virtue of
being about certain groups of spatio-temporal parts, groups either in the same time
'plane' or in the same space 'plane,' -- then Taylor A and Taylor B are correct
and analogous. (That is, for example, in
Taylor B substitute 'spatio-temporal part 1 ["where spatio-temporal part 1
is composed of smaller spatio-temporal parts 0, 0.1, 0.2,..., 1] of 0-1' for
'spatial part 1 of 0-1' in order to get the corresponding part of Garlikov
B.) We would do this normally
conceptually anyway, though we may not, of course, be aware that we are doing
so. For example, it is tempting: to
speak of me now as a temporal part of the object Rick Garlikov (or as noted before, as the whole object Rick
Garlikov) when actually this temporal part of me now is the collection of
spatio-temporal parts of Rick Garlikov at the present or now. In short, Meiland has helped show that
Taylor’s use of the terms temporal parts and spatial parts needed further
explicating. But I do not think Meiland
has successfully pointed up any disanalogy between time and space. I now, however, would like to present
a rather simple example of how time and space or temporal and spatial relations
seem disanalogous. I say seem, because perhaps they really are analogous, but
that we have not yet discovered that time really is or can be correctly
represented as three-dimensional. For
that is the difference-that space seems to be three-dimensional (although it
perhaps can be represented one- or two-dimensionally) whereas time seems to be
only one-dimensional. To put this into
Taylor's type of statement, consider the following as one (perhaps the
simplest) example of stating three-dimensionality: At any time, Tx, there can
be four objects (or four spatio-temporal parts of (an) object(s) ) 01, 02, 03, 04
such that the spatial distance from 01 to 02 equals the
spatial distance from 02 to 03, which equals the spatial
distance from 03 to 04 which equals the spatial distance
from 01 to 03 which equals the spatial distance from O2
to 04 which equals the spatial distance from O1 to 04
= x (where x is greater than zero). Such a description fits the vertices of a regular tetrahedron. The temporal analogue would have to be: At
any place, Px there can be four objects (or four spatio-temporal parts
of (an) object(s) ) 01, 02,
03, 04 such that the temporal distance from 01
to 02 equals the temporal distance from 02 to 03, which
equals the temporal distance from 03 to 04 which equals
the temporal distance from 01
to 03 which equals the temporal distance from O2 to 04
which equals the temporal distance from O1 to 04 = X
(where X is greater than zero). But what objects or parts of (an)
object(s) could this represent? It is
easy to see how one object or spatio-temporal part can be separated equally
from two others by the same amount of time -- e.g., me now from me last year
and me next year; but it is not easy to
see how four objects or spatio-temporal parts can all be equally separated from
each other in time. Hence, in this
regard, it seems time and space or temporal and spatial relations are not
analogous,
[1] Richard
Taylor, "Spatial and Temporal
Analogies and the Concept of Identity" in Problems of Space and Time,
ed. J.J.C.Smart p. 581. First published in The Journal of Philosophy,
Vol. 52 (1955) also in part in
Taylor's Metaphysics
[2] J.W.Meiland,
"Temporal Parts and Spatio-temporal Analogies," American Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 5, Number 1, January 1966
[3] For
a different criticism of Meiland's paper, see Daniel Sedey's "Being
Partial to Objects" Journal of
Philosophy, Vol. LXIV, Number 6, March 30,
1967
[4] O1 = spatio-temporal part N of O1; O2 = spatio-temporal part G of O2;
O1 = spatio-temporal part S of O1;
O2 = spatio-temporal part H of O2;
[5] “There’s
Rick,” not “There’s Rick’s face [as a baby or now]. Or “There’s Rick,” not “There’s the present
part of Rick or Rick’s present form [as an adult or as a baby].
|