As always, please give me a helpful vote here.
|
|
| ||||||||||||||||
An Amazing and Suprising Work.,
Amazon Verified
Purchase(What's this?)
This
review is from: In
Defense of the Indians: The Defense of the Most Reverend Lord, Don Fray
Bartolome De Las Casas, of the Order of Preachers, Late Bishop of Chiapa
(Paperback)
I am presently reading my way through the history of
Catholicism and slavery. Naturally, Bartolome De Las Casas' name has come up
repeatedly, generally as a witness to and critic of the Spanish treatment of the
Indians. De Las Casas' vivid descriptions of the butchery of the Indians is
often used by those who are critical of the West and of the Catholic
church.So, I was prepared to slog my way through serial accounts of Spanish brutalization of the Indians. I was surprised to find that this book - In Defense of the Indians - is not an account of that brutalization, but is a work of a first rank Thomist humanist. This text is, in fact, nothing less than a legal brief, which argues that the Spanish continual wars on the Indian populations was unjustified under either Natural Law or Christian principles. Along the way, De Las Casas redeemed my faith in Christianity and reason. De Las Casas seems to have been a phenomenal man. The professor in a lecture series I'm listening to through the Teaching Company on the Conquest of the New World called De Las Casas the greatest man in Spanish history. De Las Casas was born in 1484 and went to the West Indies in 1502 with his father, where he became a slave owner. His experience caused him to repudiate slavery, first of the Indians, and then all slavery. He gave up his slaves and "encomienca" - the Spanish practice of granting alotments of Indians for labor and tax purposes - and became an ardent defender of the Indians. De Las Casas travelled across the Atlantic 15 times in order to press his case on behalf of the Indians. He truly was a remarkable man. De Las Casas opens his book with a discussion of the classic Aristotelian position that it was just to enslave barbarians. De Las Casas points out that there are many kinds of barbarians, but that the barbarians of whom Aristotle had in mind - people who had no paractical abilty to govern themselves - are out of the norm for human beings, who are rational beings, and therefore it is unreasonable to enalave all Indians on that basis. De Las Casas therefore argues for the humanity of the Indian people, something which was controversial at the time, albeit the humanity of the Indians was recognized by the Catholic Church in Sublimis Dei in 1537. De Las Casas also provides sophisticated arguments about why the idolatry and human sacrifice of the Indians did not justify Spanish wars of conquest. The arguments he makes are rigorous and deeply informed by the philosopy of Aquinas. As an example of how to "do" practical Thomistics, De Las Casas' work is exemplary. I was put in mind that De Las Casas' arguments that the sins and crimes of another culture do not justify intervention into that culture is one that we moderns might learn from. In many ways, De las Casas comes across as the true humanist and authentic multi-culturalist. De Las Casas was not a multi-culturalist based on a lack of confidence in his own culture; he firmly affirms the truth of Christianity. He did, however, believe that religious faith could not be compelled. His repeated point throughout his work is that the Spanish should win the hearts and souls of the Indians by presenting themselves as true Christians and by teaching the Indians. He also repeatedly decries how the barbarism of the Spanish was having the effect of alienating Indians from the Christian faith. One interesting side-note I picked up from De Las Casas was the way that the medieval mind distinguished between heretics and non-believers. While De Las Casas viewed non-believers as outside the jurisdiction of the Church, such was not the case with heretics. Heretics were people who had given a solemn oath in baptism to adhere to Christian beliefs and to the Christian church. Heretics were therefore nothing less than oath-breakers, who could be compelled to their oath in the same way as a person who breached a contract could be compelled to perform. I don't believe that I'd heard that point before, but once explained it seems like a position that might under some circumstances be held as plausible and it does provide a window into understanding phenomena like the Inquisition. This is a great book for those interested in understanding the past, or who have a background in Thomism, or who appreciate a well-constructed rational argument. |